Showing posts with label Austrian school. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Austrian school. Show all posts

Sunday, June 5, 2011

The Neoclassical Wing of the Austrian School

J. G. Hülsmann describes role of Friedrich von Wieser, the first generation Austrian after Menger:
“It is in this light that one has to see Wieser’s personal impact on the education of the rising generations of Austrian economists. [sc. Wieser] … held Menger’s former position from 1903 to 1920 and continued to teach as an emeritus until his death in 1926. During this entire period, it was Wieser who taught the introductory courses in economic science at the University of Vienna. Until 1914, Böhm-Bawerk’s presence provided some counterbalance, but after his death, Wieser’s position was that of an unquestioned authority in all matters of general economic theory, a position reinforced by the publication that same year of his general treatise, Theorie der gesellschaftlichen Wirtschaft.

The entire fourth generation of Austrian economists—brilliant young men like Hayek, Machlup, Haberler, Morgenstern, and Rosenstein-Rodan—were thus shaped by the Wieserian mold before they set off on their own intellectual paths. Largely ignorant of Menger’s Principles (out of print since the 1880s), they were trained in the spirit of the neoclassical synthesis. As a result of these circumstances, there was strictly speaking no fourth generation of “Austrian” economists in the Mengerian sense. All the young men who are commonly held to be fourth-generation members were in fact lost to the neoclassical school—with the possible exception of Hayek, who decades later rediscovered some Mengerian themes in his work on the Counterrevolution of Science (1954)” (Hülsmann 2007: 160–161).
Hülsmann is making quite a claim here. I suppose these would be his “fourth generation of Austrian economists”:
Fourth Generation of the Austrian School
Friedrich August von Hayek 1889–1992
Oskar Morgenstern 1902–1976
Gottfried von Haberler 1900–1995
Fritz Machlup 1902–1983
Ewald Schams 1899–1955
Paul N. Rosenstein-Rodan 1902–1985.
This generation of Austrians were “lost to the neoclassical school.” So the question arises: were they even Austrians at all then?

This also raises the question of why Hayek’s business cycle theory work in the 1930s, which is obviously macroeconomic theorizing requiring neoclassical notions of general equilibrium, remains such an important part of Austrian theory:
“Previous to [sc. 1937] ... Hayek’s own thought was dominated by General Equilibrium theory. This comes out repeatedly in Monetary Theory and the Trade Cycle (1929; English edition 1933), where he talks of ‘the unquestionable methods of equilibrium’ (p. 57), and also in Prices and Production. He says, ‘it is my conviction that if one wants to explain economic phenomena at all we have no means available but to build on the foundations given by the concept of a tendency toward equilibrium’ ... . Hayek points out in a footnote that by equilibrium he means the Lausanne formulation of General Equilibrium” (McCloughry 1984: viii).
And, as Lachmann argued:
“Professor Hayek and Mises both espouse the market process, but do not ignore equilibrium as its final stage. The former, whose early work was clearly under the influence of the general equilibrium model, at one time appeared to regard a strong tendency towards general equilibrium as a real phenomenon of the market economy. Mises, calling the Austrians ‘logical’ and neoclassicals ‘mathematical’ economists, wrote: ‘Both the logical and the mathematical economists assert that human action ultimately aims at the establishment of such a state of equilibrium and would reach it if all further changes in data were to cease’ … . It is this view of the market process as at least potentially terminating in a state of long-run general equilibrium that now appears to require revision” (Lachmann 1976: 60–61).
The influence of general equilibrium theory on both Wieser and Hayek is also supported by Salerno (2002).

To the extent that Hayek relies on Walrasian general equilibrium theory, he is subject to the critique of that theory in Post Keynesian economics. Hayek also used Wicksellian ideas on monetary equilibrium and the natural rate of interest, concepts that are also invalid (for a statement of how Wicksellian monetary theory can be overthrown by issues related to the Cambridge capital controversies, see Rogers 1989: 21–44).

I just starting to read Robert L. Vienneau, “Some Fallacies of Austrian Economics” (September 2006), and he provides a critique of Austrian business cycle theory from the perspective of Post Keynesian theory as well, particularly the Cambridge capital controversies.


BIBLIOGRAPHY

Butos, W. N. 1985. “Hayek and General Equilibrium Analysis,” Southern Economic Journal 52.2: 332–343.

Hülsmann, J. G. 2007. Mises: The Last Knight of Liberalism, Ludwig von Mises Institute, Auburn, Ala.

Lachmann, L. M. 1976. “From Mises to Shackle: An Essay on Austrian Economics and the Kaleidic Society,” Journal of Economic Literature 14.1: 54-62.

McCloughry, R. 1984. “Editor’s Introduction,” in F. A. von Hayek, Money, Capital & Fluctuations: Early Essays (ed. by R. McCloughry), Routledge & Kegan Paul, London. vii–x.

Rogers, C. 1989. Money, Interest and Capital: A Study in the Foundations of Monetary Theory, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Salerno, J. T. 2002. “Friedrich von Wieser and Friedrich A. Hayek: The General Equilibrium Tradition in Austrian Economics,” Journal des Economistes et des Etudes Humaines 12.2: 357–377.

Vienneau, R. L. 2006. “Some Fallacies of Austrian Economics,” September
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=921183

Vienneau, R. L. 2010. “Some Capital-Theoretic Fallacies in Garrison’s Exposition of Austrian Business Cycle Theory,” September 4
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1671886

Friday, June 3, 2011

Why are there no Austrian Socialists?

That is the title of an article by P. J. Boettke (1995; reprinted in Boettke 2000), and I have just finished reading it. While that article is a rich and genuinely interesting treatment of a myriad of topics – such as ethics, claims about the value-free nature of Austrian economics, and economic methodology – Boettke makes a point early on in the article that deserves further analysis:
“Wieser may have been a mild Fabian in political persuasion, but his insight concerning how the decentralized decisions in the private market economy would outperform a centralized economy precisely because of the ‘knowledge problem’ in the latter would become a theme repeatedly stressed by subsequent generations of Austrians in their battles with advocates of socialist and interventionist policies” (Boettke 1995: 36–37).
It is perfectly true that if by “socialist” we mean “Marxist” or “Communist,” then there are no Austrian advocates of “socialism.” If by “socialist” one means “social democrat” or an advocate of a mixed economy, then it is clear that one wing of the early Austrian school was actually compatible with social democracy.

Hayek was once asked about the 1920s history of the Austrian school, and his answer is instructive:
“LEIJONHUFVUD: In economics, let me come back to a question we have touched upon before. In the twenties in Vienna, was there such a thing as an Austrian school in economics? Did you and your contemporaries perceive identification with a school?

HAYEK: Yes, yes. Although at the same time [we were] very much aware of the division between not only Meyer and Mises but already [Friedrich von] Wieser and Mises. You see, we were very much aware that there were two traditions—the [Eugen von] Böhm-Bawerk tradition and the Wieser tradition—and Mises was representing the Böhm-Bawerk tradition, and Meyer was representing the Wieser tradition.

LEIJONHUFVUD: And where did the line between the two go? Was there a political or politically ideological line involved?

HAYEK: Very little. Böhm-Bawerk had already been an outright liberal, and Mises even more, while Wieser was slightly tainted with Fabian socialist sympathies. In fact, it was his great pride to have given the scientific foundation for progressive taxation. But otherwise there wasn’t really—I mean, Wieser, of course, would have claimed to be liberal, but he was using it much more in a later sense, not a classical liberal (Nobel Prize-Winning Economist: Friedrich A. von Hayek (1983), pp. 49–50).
In other words, there was a split in the Austrian school in the 1920s between (1) the classical liberal wing of Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk/Mises (which evolved into modern American libertarianism), and (2) the wing of von Wieser, whose members (or at least some of them) were leaning towards Fabian socialism, and was clearly becoming more like modern progressive liberalism or social democracy (see also Shearmur 1996: 29). Hayek claims that there were “very little” political differences between the two wings, and yet if we turn to the role of Eugen von Philippovich von Philippsberg (1858–1917), it looks like a different story to me.

Eugen von Philippovich von Philippsberg was a student of Carl Menger, and then taught at the University of Freiburg im Breisgau. He returned to the University of Vienna in 1893 as a professor of economics (Hülsmann 2007: 83). Philippovich was already in favour of state intervention before he taught at Vienna, and on his return as a Professor in 1893,
he immediately joined the Vienna Fabians. The group organized public conferences and discussions to promote the idea of government intervention in the service of a “social” agenda, which primarily concerned the support of the working-class poor. Philippovich’s personal and intellectual qualities made him the center of the Vienna Fabians and helped spread their influence among academics and businessmen. These activities were so successful that Fabian ideas eventually were incorporated into the programs of all Austrian political parties” (Hülsmann 2007: 83).
So we have an early Austrian who was an explicit member of the Vienna Fabians and was the “center of the Vienna Fabians.” In fact, von Philippovich was at the centre of the Austrian “social” liberal movement:
“Against the seeming hopelessness and isolation of classic Liberalism in German Austria, however, a new generation of younger, social Liberals evolved in Vienna in the mid- and later 1890s. The radicalism and optimism of the Viennese Fabians reflected their limited constituency responsibilities and their freedom of the constraints of membership in a large, diversified bourgeois party …. Viennese social Liberalism was rich in its associational life and in its points of intellectual and administrative influence, but its ideological and moral center point was the Social Political movement launched in 1893 by Eugen von Philippovich, Michael Hainisch, Julius Ofner, and Otto Wittelshbfer. They were soon joined by a wide circle of university academics, lawyers, and state officials, many of whom, like Josef Redlich, wrote for the new social Liberal weekly Die Zeit. These Viennese Fabians were of crucial importance in determining the course of the final generation of Austrian Liberalism before the war. Philippovich especially, with his irenic attempt to reconcile the historicism of Schmoller and the more theoretical, classical traditions of Austrian economics, served at the University of Vienna as a powerful moral and pedagogical influence on hundreds of young academics, journalists, and government bureaucrats after 1893 in reviving a semblance of post-Liberal bourgeois culture” (Boyer 1978: 76–77).
The aims of the Austrian Fabians are described in von Philippovich (1896), which, unfortunately, I can’t get hold of, but his views summed up by J. W. Boyer:
“ … the Fabians were social instrumentalists who sought to improve bourgeois society without destroying its fundamental private capitalist rationale. Much of Philippovich’s scholarly work in economics considered reformist policy questions such as housing reform, tax policy and wage rates, and social insurance for private employees as well as the more general problem of bourgeois solidarism as a mediatory mode between capitalism and socialism” (Boyer 1978: 80–81).
One can turn to von Philippovich’s writings on this, though again I have not yet read them:
Eugen von Philippovich, 1906. Grundriss der Politischen Oekonomie (vol. 1; 6th edn), Allgemeine Volkswirthschaftslehre, Tubingen (pp. 14–19; 206–209; 408–414).

Eugen von Philippovich, 1905. “Individuelle Verantwortlichkeit und gegenseitige Hilfe im Wirtschaftsleben” [“Individual Responsibility and Mutual Assistance in Economic Life”], Zeitschrift fur Volkswvirtschaft, Sozialpolitik und Verwaltung 14: 547–570.
Friedrich von Wieser was born in 1851, and took a degree from the University of Vienna in 1872. After historical interests, he came to study economics after reading Carl Menger’s Grundsatze (for Wieser’s life, see Schumpeter 1997: 298ff; Schumpeter and Achille Loria 1927). From 1903 he succeeded Menger at the University of Vienna where he taught economics along with his brother-in-law Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk. Friedrich von Wieser was the teacher of Friedrich August von Hayek. A. O. Ebenstein, in his Friedrich Hayek: A Biography (Chicago, 2003), provides a good summary of von Wieser’s economics:
“Wieser was more corporatist and intervention-minded than Böhm-Bawerk and Menger. Hayek recalled that when he was a student, he was ‘very much aware that there were two traditions’ in the Austrian school — the ‘Böhm-Bawerk tradition and the Wieser tradition. Wieser was slightly tainted with Fabian socialist sympathies. Hayek observed of his later relationship with Mises, who ‘represented the Böhm-Bawerk tradition,’ that ‘I perhaps most profited from his teaching because I came to him as a trained economist, trained in a parallel branch of Austrian economics from which he gradually, but never completely, won me over” (Ebenstein 2003: 26).
Moreover, according to Hayek, classical liberalism/libertarianism was not the major or defining ideology in the discussion group called the “Geistkreis” that Hayek and J. Herbert Fürth founded in 1921:
LEIJONHUFVUD: Now, in the twenties, were most of the economists in Vienna at that time liberals in the traditional sense?

HAYEK: No, no. Very few. Strigl was not; he was, if anything, a socialist. Shams was not. Morgenstern—was not. I think it reduces to Haberler, Machlup, and myself.

LEIJONHUFVUD: So my previous question was: Was there an Austrian school? and you said yes, definitely.

HAYEK: Theoretically, yes.

LEIJONHUFVUD: In theory.

HAYEK: In that sense, the term, the meaning of the term, has changed. At that time, we would use the term Austrian school quite irrespective of the political consequences which grew from it. It was the marginal utility analysis which to us was the Austrian school.

LEIJONHUFVUD: Deriving from Menger, via either Wieser or Bohm-Bawerk?

HAYEK: Yes, yes.

LEIJONHUFVUD: The association with liberal ideological beliefs was not yet there?

HAYEK: Well, the Menger/Bohm-Bawerk/Mises tradition had always been liberal, but that was not regarded as the essential attribute of the Austrian school. It was that wing which was the liberal wing of the school.

LEIJONHUFVUD: And the Geistkreis was not predominately liberal?

HAYEK: No, far from it.

LEIJONHUFVUD: And what about Mises’s seminar?

HAYEK: Again, not. I mean you had [Ewald] Schams and Strigl there; and Engel-Janoschi, the historian; and Kaufmann, who certainly was not in any sense a liberal; Schutz, who hardly was—he was perhaps closer to us; Voegelin, who was not ….

LEIJONHUFVUD: So in the revival of interest in the Austrian school that has taken place in recent years in the United States …

HAYEK: It means the Mises school (Nobel Prize-Winning Economist: Friedrich A. von Hayek, pp. 54–56).
According to Hayek, it was “marginal utility analysis” that was the defining attribute of the Austrian school, not Classical liberalism. And Hayek himself had been an adherent of Fabian socialism as Wieser’s student in the 1920s before he was influenced by Mises (Ebenstein 2003: 40–41).

So what we in fact have is four early Austrians who were connected to Fabian socialism:
(1) Eugen von Philippovich, a leader of Austrian social liberalism;
(2) Friedrich von Wieser;
(3) the early Hayek, and
(4) Richard von Strigl (who was, according to Hayek, “if anything, a socialist”).
There were Austrian socialists of the social democratic variety, and modern Austrians have ignored them, and questions about how early Austrian economics was compatible with Fabian socialism. A more serious question would also be: why are there no Austrian social democrats today?

These seem like promising research questions to me.

Appendix: The Early Austrian School



BIBLIOGRAPHY

Boettke, P. J. 1995. “Why are there no Austrian socialists? Ideology, science and the Austrian school,” Journal of the History of Economic Thought 17: 35–56.

Boettke, P. J. 2000. Calculation and Coordination: Essays on Socialism and Transitional Political Economy, Routledge, New York. 7–28.

Boyer, J. W. 1978. “Freud, Marriage, and Late Viennese Liberalism: A Commentary from 1905,” Journal of Modern History 50.1: 72–102.

Ebenstein, A. O. 2003. Friedrich Hayek: A Biography, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

Hülsmann, J. G. 2007. Mises: The Last Knight of Liberalism, Ludwig von Mises Institute, Auburn, Ala.

Nobel Prize-Winning Economist: Friedrich A. von Hayek. Interviewed by Earlene Graver, Axel Leijonhufvud, Leo Rosten, Jack High, James Buchanan, Robert Bork, Thomas Hazlett, Armen A. Alchian, Robert Chitester, Regents of the University of California, 1983.

Philippovich, Eugen von, 1896. “Alt- und Neu-Oesterreich,” Die Zeit (August 29).

Philippovich, Eugen von, 1905. “Individuelle Verantwortlichkeit und gegenseitige Hilfe im Wirtschaftsleben” [“Individual Responsibility and Mutual Assistance in Economic Life”] Zeitschrift fur Volkswvirtschaft, Sozialpolitik und Verwaltung 14: 547–570.

Philippovich, Eugen von, 1906. Grundriss der Politischen Oekonomie (vol. 1; 6th edn), Allgemeine Volkswirthschaftslehre, Tubingen.

Schumpeter, J. A. 1997. Ten Great Economists (rev. edn), Routledge, London.

Schumpeter, J. and J. B. Achille Loria, 1927. “Obituary: Friedrich von Wieser,” Economic Journal 37.146: 328–335.

Shearmur, J. 1996. Hayek and After: Hayekian Liberalism as a Research Programme, Routledge, London.

Thursday, June 2, 2011

Questions for Austrians Before You Debate Them

The Austrian school has different branches and sometimes conflicting doctrines (see “The Different Types of Austrian Economics,” December 5, 2010).

Before you debate an Austrian or an Austrian apologist, there are a number of questions you can profitably ask to properly understand that person’s brand of Austrian economics.

These are as follows:
(1) Are you (a) a small state Classical liberal Misesian or (b) an anarcho-capitalist in the tradition of Rothbard and Hoppe?

(2) If (a) what functions do you think the state should have?

(3) What is your view of ethics? Do you support natural rights/natural law theory or some form of utilitarianism/consequentialism? If neither, then what theory?

(4) Are you (a) a moderate subjectivist in the tradition of Kirzner/ O’Driscoll and Rizzo or (b) a radical subjectivist in the tradition of Lachmann?

(5) Do you think expectations are subjective, as Lachmann contends?

(6) Do you think (a) Mises’s praxeology is the proper methodology for Austrian economics or (b) follow Hayek or O’Driscoll and Rizzo in rejecting pure praxeology and apriorism and wanting a greater role for empirical evidence?
Though there is a major split in the Austrian school between radical subjectivists and moderate subjectivists, it seems to me that either group can adhere to anarcho-capitalism. I am actually interested to know how many of the neo-Austrian moderate subjectivists support a minimal state.

Here is a list of older and modern neo-Austrians. If anyone knows their positions on the questions above, I would like to hear them.

Hans F. Sennholz (1922–2007)
Israel M. Kirzner (1930– )
Andrew Schotter
Laurence S. Moss
Walter E. Block (1941– )
Roger Garrison (1944– )
Karen I. Vaughn (1944– )
Mark Skousen (1947– )
Gerald P. O’Driscoll (1947– )
Don C. Lavoie (1951–2001)
Joseph T. Salerno
Richard M. Ebeling (1950– )
Mario Rizzo
William L. Anderson
Roger Koppl
Peter J. Boettke (1960– )
David L. Prychitko (1962– )
Steven Horwitz (1964– ; Hayekian anarchist, consequentialist, subjective expectations)
Steve Kates
Robert P. Murphy (1976– )
Jonathan M. Finegold Catalan