Thursday, February 11, 2016

Marx’s Capital, Volume 1, Chapter 12: A Critical Summary

Updated
Chapter 12 of volume 1 of Capital is called “The Concept of Relative Surplus Value” and it deals with yet further aspects of surplus value.

Marx points to another way of increasing surplus value. He considers this representation of the working day:
Working Day 1: A-----------B--C

Working Day 2: A-----B′---B--C
AB represents the necessary labour-time equivalent to the value of maintaining and reproducing workers. BC therefore represents surplus labour.

In Working Day 2, the total length of the working day stays the same but a business can lower the amount of time in AB to AB′ (Marx 1990: 429), which is the necessary labour-time equivalent to the value of maintaining and reproducing workers.

We must remember here how Marx defines the value of labour-power:
“We have seen that the labourer, during one portion of the labour-process, produces only the value of his labour-power, that is, the value of his means of subsistence.” (Marx 1906: 239).

“The value of labour-power resolves itself into the value of a definite quantity of the means of subsistence. It therefore varies with the value of these means or with the quantity of labour requisite for their production.” (Marx 1906: 191).
Although a capitalist can lower his money wages to workers, if the wage is lowered below the value of maintaining and reproducing workers, then the very reproduction of workers is impaired (Marx 1990: 431). Self-sustaining capitalism and capitalist accumulation therefore cannot reduce wages below subsistence level on an economy-wide scale, though individual capitalists may attempt to do so (Marx 1990: 431). That is, Marx states that some real-world capitalists do sometimes lower wages below the value of labour-power (which is another cause of the downward pressure on wages), but Marx implies that it cannot be a viable and consistent method of increasing surplus labour, because it would destroy the labour force (Marx 1990: 431).

We see this point in the passage below as well as Marx’s assumption that all commodities exchange at their true labour values:
“Despite the important part which this method plays in actual practice [that is, lowering wages below subsistence], we are excluded from considering it in this place, by our assumption, that all commodities, including labour-power, are bought and sold at their full value. Granted this, it follows that the labour-time necessary for the production of labour-power, or for the reproduction of its value, cannot be lessened by a fall in the labourer’s wages below the value of his labour-power, but only by a fall in this value itself. Given the length of the working day, the prolongation of the surplus-labour must of necessity originate in the curtailment of the necessary labour-time; the latter cannot arise from the former. …

Such a fall in the value of labour-power implies, however, that the same necessaries of life which were formerly produced in ten hours, can now be produced in nine hours. But this is impossible without an increase in the productiveness of labour. For example, suppose a shoemaker, with given tools, makes in one working day of twelve hours, one pair of boots. If he must make two pairs in the same time, the productiveness of his labour must be doubled; and this cannot be done, except by an alteration in his tools or in his mode of working, or in both. Hence, the conditions of production, i.e., his mode of production, and the labour-process itself, must be revolutionised. By increase in the productiveness of labour, we mean, generally, an alteration in the labour-process, of such a kind as to shorten the labour-time socially necessary for the production of a commodity, and to endow a given quantity of labour with the power of producing a greater quantity of use-value.” (Marx 1906: 344–345).
We must remember that in volume 1 Marx’s “law of value” is that commodities tend to exchange at true labour values, and that the labour values are the equilibrium points around which prices fluctuate, not that commodities always and everywhere exchange at true labour values. But here in this chapter Marx is assuming that all commodities and labour-power exchange only at true labour values.

It follows that the only viable method by which a capitalist can reduce the value of AB to AB′ is by
(1) increases in productivity of labour;

(2) falls in the value and price of basic commodities needed for maintaining and reproducing workers, and

(3) a resulting fall in money wages.
Note well that if (3) money wages are not eventually reduced, then capitalists cannot obtain the money value of their increased relative surplus value.

Marx now introduces a distinction between (1) absolute surplus-value and (2) relative surplus-value:
“The surplus-value produced by prolongation of the working day, I call absolute surplus-value. On the other hand, the surplus-value arising from the curtailment of the necessary labour-time, and from the corresponding alteration in the respective lengths of the two components of the working day, I call relative surplus-value.

In order to effect a fall in the value of labour-power, the increase in the productiveness of labour must seize upon those branches of industry, whose products determine the value of labour-power, and consequently either belong to the class of customary means of subsistence, or are capable of supplying the place of those means. But the value of a commodity is determined, not only by the quantity of labour which the labourer directly bestows upon that commodity, but also by the labour contained in the means of production. For instance, the value of a pair of boots depends, not only on the cobbler’s labour, but also on the value of the leather, wax, thread, &c. Hence, a fall in the value of labour-power is also brought about by an increase in the productiveness of labour, and by a corresponding cheapening of commodities in those industries which supply the instruments of labour and the raw material, that form the material elements of the constant capital required for producing the necessaries of life. But an increase in the productiveness of labour in those branches of industry which supply neither the necessaries of life, nor the means of production for such necessaries, leaves the value of labour-power undisturbed.

The cheapened commodity, of course, causes only a pro tanto fall in the value of labour-power, a fall proportional to the extent of that commodity’s employment in the reproduction of labour-power. Shirts, for instance, are a necessary means of subsistence, but are only one out of many. The totality of the necessaries of life consists, however, of various commodities, each the product of a distinct industry; and the value of each of those commodities enters as a component part into the value of labour-power. This latter value decreases with the decrease of the labour-time necessary for its reproduction; the total decrease being the sum of all the different curtailments of labour-time effected in those various and distinct industries. This general result is treated, here, as if it were the immediate result directly aimed at in each individual case. Whenever an individual capitalist cheapens shirts, for instance, by increasing the productiveness of labour, he by no means necessarily aims at reducing the value of labour-power and shortening, pro tanto, the necessary labour-time. But it is only in so far as he ultimately contributes to this result, that he assists in raising the general rate of surplus-value. The general and necessary tendencies of capital must be distinguished from their forms of manifestation.

It is not our intention to consider, here, the way in which the laws, immanent in capitalist production, manifest themselves in the movements of individual masses of capital, where they assert themselves as coercive laws of competition, and are brought home to the mind and consciousness of the individual capitalist as the directing motives of his operations. But this much is clear; a scientific analysis of competition is not possible, before we have a conception of the inner nature of capital, just as the apparent motions of the heavenly bodies are not intelligible to any but him, who is acquainted with their real motions, motions which are not directly perceptible by the senses.” (Marx 1906: 345–347).
But there is a fundamental additional point: if the productivity of labour decreases the value of commodities so that the value of maintaining and reproducing workers also decreases, then it follows that in the long run money wages should fall, because the prices of fundamental commodities necessary for the maintaining and reproducing of workers will also be falling.

As productivity and new technology used in production cheapens commodities in these innovative industries, these production methods spread to the whole sector and the price of commodities falls, so that these latter prices reflect the new abstract, socially necessary labour time (or “social labour”) required to produce these commodities.

This point is made clear by Marx as follows:
“The real value of a commodity is, however, not its individual value but its social value; that is to say, the real value is not measured by the labour-time that the article in each individual case costs the producer, but by the labour-time socially required for its production. If therefore, the capitalist who applies the new method, sells his commodity at its social value of one shilling, he sells it for threepence above its individual value, and thus realises an extra surplus-value of threepence. On the other hand, the working day of 12 hours is, as regards him, now represented by 24 articles instead of 12. Hence, in order to get rid of the product of one working day, the demand must be double what it was, i.e., the market must become twice as extensive. Other things being equal, his commodities can command a more extended market only by a diminution of their prices. He will therefore sell them above their individual but under their social value, say at tenpence each. By this means he still squeezes an extra surplus-value of one penny out of each. This augmentation of surplus-value is pocketed by him, whether his commodities belong or not to the class of necessary means of subsistence that participate in determining the general value of labour-power. Hence, independently of this latter circumstance, there is a motive for each individual capitalist to cheapen his commodities, by increasing the productiveness of labour.” (Marx 1906: 348).

“Hence, the capitalist who applies the improved method of production appropriates to surplus-labour a greater portion of the working day, than the other capitalists in the same trade. He does individually, what the whole body of capitalists engaged in producing relative surplus-value, do collectively. On the other hand, however, this extra surplus-value vanishes, so soon as the new method of production has become general and has consequently caused the difference between the individual value of the cheapened commodity and its social value to vanish. The law of the determination of value by labour-time, a law which brings under its sway the individual capitalist who applies the new method of production, by compelling him to sell his goods under their social value, this same law, acting as a coercive law of competition, forces his competitors to adopt the new method. The general rate of surplus-value is, therefore, ultimately affected by the whole process, only when the increase in the productiveness of labour, has seized upon those branches of production that are connected with, and has cheapened those commodities that form part of, the necessary means of subsistence, and are therefore elements of the value of labour-power.

The value of commodities is in inverse ratio to the productiveness of labour. And so, too, is the value of labour-power, because it depends on the values of commodities. Relative surplus-value is, on the contrary, directly proportional to that productiveness. It rises with rising and falls with falling productiveness. The value of money being assumed to be constant, an average social working day of 12 hours always produces the same new value, six shillings, no matter how this sum may be apportioned between surplus-value and wages. But if, in consequence of increased productiveness, the value of the necessaries of life fall, and the value of a day’s labour-power be thereby reduced from five shillings to three, the surplus-value increases from one shilling to three. Ten hours were necessary for the reproduction of the value of the labour-power; now only six are required. Four hours have been set free, and can be annexed to the domain of surplus-labour. Hence there is immanent in capital an inclination and constant tendency, to heighten the productiveness of labour, in order to cheapen commodities, and by such cheapening to cheapen the labourer himself.

The value of a commodity is, in itself, of no interest to the capitalist. What alone interests him, is the surplus-value that dwells in it, and is realisable by sale. Realisation of the surplus-value necessarily carries with it the refunding of the value that was advanced. … relative surplus-value increases in direct proportion to the development of the productiveness of labour, while, on the other hand, the value of commodities diminishes in the same proportion; since one and the same process cheapens commodities, and augments the surplus-value contained in them; … .”(Marx 1906: 350–351).
So when a new, more productive technique is introduced by an individual capitalist, for a while he can continue to sell the commodity at the older price reflecting the average social labour embodied in the commodity and so obtain higher profits, but eventually the new method will spread, and social value and prices will fall (Brewer 1984: 49–50; Harvey 2010: 168). Note well that this theory is dependent on the view that commodities tend to exchange at true labour values. Once the alternative theory of price determination that Marx used in volume 3 of Capital is applied, then it must be re-formulated, for virtually all prices deviate from true labour values when prices of production are the anchors for the price system.

There is also another point: Marx seems to think that the capitalist who sells his commodity at the older price reflecting the average social labour even when his individual business has a lower labour value for the commodity gains additional surplus value (Marx 1906: 348), but it is unclear where this surplus value comes from, since his individual business cannot be producing it. In volume 3, Marx thinks that surplus value is redistributed between firms.

But to return to Marx’s argument: what Marx is saying is that capitalism has a “constant tendency” to cheapen the commodities necessary for the value of maintaining and reproducing workers (that is, the value of labour-power) and so to decrease the wages of workers, because for Marx wages tend towards the value of labour-power (Brewer 1984: 50). By this development, capitalists gain greater relative surplus value, and it follows that wages must tend towards the value of maintaining and reproducing workers.

Therefore machines – while not a source of surplus value – nevertheless can be used to extract more relative surplus value from labour (Harvey 2010: 169).

That Marx is thinking of wages being reduced as the value of commodities necessary for maintaining and reproducing workers falls is clear from his footnote:
“‘In whatever proportion the expenses of a labourer are diminished, in the same proportion will his wages be diminished, if the restraints upon industry are at the same time taken off.’ (‘Considerations concerning taking off of the Bounty on Corn Exported,’ &c, Lond., 1753, p. 7.) ‘The interest of trade requires, that corn and all provisions should be as cheap as possible; for whatever makes them dear, must make labour dear also ... in all countries where industry is not restrained the price of provisions must affect the price of labour. This will always be diminished when the necessaries of life grow cheaper.’ (1. c. p. 3.) ‘Wages are decreased in the same proportion as the powers of production increase. Machinery, it is true, cheapens the necessaries of life, but it also cheapens the labourer.’ (‘A Prize Essay on the Comparative Merits of Competition and Co-operation.’ London, 1834, p. 27.)” (Marx 1906: 351, n. 1).
But there is a gaping and devastating hole in Marx’s analysis: the real world tendency in capitalism of downward nominal wage rigidity. This was apparent even by the late 19th century, as I have demonstrated here, here, here, and here.

In Britain, even as prices were falling spectacularly (especially of basic commodities) in the 1873 to 1896 period, money wages were becoming sticky, and the real wage was soaring.

We can see this in the graphs below. The first shows an index of average British money wages from 1850 to 1902 (with data from Wood 1909: 102–103).


As we can see, money wages had become relatively inflexible downwards by about 1878, even as the deflation continued until 1896. And the long-run trend was of rising money wages. This is the opposite of what we would expect if Marx’s theories were true, for then money wages would tend to consistently fall if general price deflation was in progress. Wages would tend towards the value of maintaining and reproducing labour-power, but this has been spectacularly contradicted by the reality of capitalism which has seen living standards for workers soar in the long run.

In the second graph below, Wood’s data (Wood 1909: 102–103, Appendix) on UK real wages from 1850 to 1902 (constructed from the wage data for working people in a whole range of industries) shows us that the real wage soared.


Marx’s theory of wages in capitalism and the idea that the worker is constantly “cheapened” have been refuted by history: moreover, they were refuted even by the end of the 19th century.

Finally, Marx sees this as the inherent tendency of capitalism:
“The shortening of the working day is, therefore, by no means what is aimed at, in capitalist production, when labour is economised by increasing its productiveness. …. The object of all development of the productiveness of labour, within the limits of capitalist production, is to shorten that part of the working day, during which the workman must labour for his own benefit, and by that very shortening, to lengthen the other part of the day, during which he is at liberty to work gratis for the capitalist.” (Marx 1906: 352).
So, according to this, machines only increase the relative surplus labour extracted from the workers, and the aim of productivity gains is not to shorten the working day, but to reduce the money wage (from reducing the value of labour-power) so that capitalists gain more relative surplus value.

This is nonsense, since capitalists are not in search of some mystical surplus value and the very concept of socially necessary labour time is incoherent and cannot even be properly defined (e.g., it is subject to a host of problems and a devastating aggregation problem as noted here).

Capitalists seek money profits and market share, but, as many have discovered, this can be achieved by raising money wages in line with productivity growth and actively creating their profit level by means of a profit mark-up on average unit costs.

That Marx badly missed the real world trajectory of capitalism can be seen in his doomsday predictions at the end of volume 1 of Capital in the “Historical Tendency of Capitalist Accumulation” chapter about the plight of the working class and the inevitability of socialism:
“Along with the constantly diminishing number of the magnates of capital, who usurp and monopolise all advantages of this process of transformation, grows the mass of misery, oppression, slavery, degradation, exploitation; but with this too grows the revolt of the working-class, a class always increasing in numbers, and disciplined, united, organised by the very mechanism of the process of capitalist production itself. The monopoly of capital becomes a fetter upon the mode of production, which has sprung up and flourished along with, and under it. Centralisation of the means of production and socialisation of labour at last reach a point where they become incompatible with their capitalist integument. This integument is burst asunder. The knell of capitalist private property sounds. The expropriators are expropriated.” (Marx 1906: 836–837).
But if capitalism can provide soaring living standards even for workers (as it did even in the 19th century), then how can the “mass of misery, oppression, slavery, degradation, [sc. and] exploitation” be constantly growing? Why would socialism be inevitable if workers see their living standards soar and the real wage soars above subsistence level?

BIBLIOGRAPHY
Brewer, Anthony. 1984. A Guide to Marx’s Capital. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Harvey, David. 2010. A Companion to Marx’s Capital. Verso, London and New York.

Marx, Karl. 1906. Capital. A Critique of Political Economy (vol. 1; rev. trans. by Ernest Untermann from 4th German edn.). The Modern Library, New York.

Marx, Karl. 1990. Capital. A Critique of Political Economy. Volume One (trans. Ben Fowkes). Penguin Books, London.

Wood, George H. 1909. “Real Wages and the Standard of Comfort since 1850,” Journal of the Royal Statistical Society 72: 91–103.

13 comments:

  1. A bust, as usual. Surprise, surprise.

    Note well that this theory is dependent on the view that commodities tend to exchange at true labour values. Once the alternative theory of price determination Marx that used in volume 3 of Capital is applied, then it falls apart, for virtually all prices deviate from true labour values when prices of production are the anchors for the price system.

    No, it's not in any way dependent on commodities exchanging at their value. Commodities exchanging for more or less than value can never violate the aggregate constraint of the law of value. And the growth of aggregate constant capital relative to aggregate variable capital necessarily pushes profitability downward.

    In essence, the numerator is a flow and the denominator is a stock, and the latter grows on the basis of, and much faster than, the former. This leads to a shrinking result.

    There is also another point: Marx seems to think that the capitalist who sells his commodity at the older price reflecting the average social labour even when his individual business has a lower labour value for the commodity gains additional surplus value (Marx 1906: 348), but it is unclear where this surplus value comes from, since his individual business cannot be producing it.

    Modern Marxists call this "super-profits," though I don't recall if Marx ever employed the term. This is the transfer of surplus value between capitals.

    If two producers make identical products, these will generally sell at the same price, regardless of whether one producer does it at half the cost of another. A 5-hour and a 10-hour production method produce the same good, with average labor time of 7.5. Assuming that they sell at value, the former nets 2.5 hours' worth of free value; the latter loses 2.5 hours' worth, effectively having provided it to the other. Assuming they do NOT sell at their value, this relationship becomes tendential rather than exact.

    Marx’s theory of wages in capitalism and the idea that the worker is constantly “cheapened” have been refuted by history

    You're making the same mistake over and over. This is just the tendency resulting from the process of capital accumulation, and not the whole picture. Say it with me: That's. Only. One. Aspect. Of. Marx's. Theory. Of. Wages. Clap between each word, if it helps.

    This is nonsense, since capitalists are not in search of some mystical surplus value and the very concept of socially necessary labour time is incoherent and cannot even be properly defined

    Wah wah wah wah.

    -Capitalists seek profit.
    -Profit is one form of surplus value.
    -Profit-maxing behavior has the emergent effect of maxing surplus value.
    -It's not incoherent at all.

    Let's run through it, in the hopes that a year may finally be enough time for you to understand a bare handful of words:

    Social: Belonging to, or directed towards the needs of, society. Wage labor is social labor, for instance, as the laborer does not wholly own the output, and the output is a use-value. "From the moment that men work for one another in any way, their labor assumes a social form."
    It is also elaborated on as a social average. An average is what you get when you add a sequence of numbers together, then divide by the number of elements in the sequence.
    Necessary: Required by the given production method.
    Labor: The productive activity that serves as humanity's metabolism with nature, to transform pieces of reality to suit our needs.
    Time: A quantified system of sequential relations between events, through which causality is expressed.
    Bonus: Abstract: The quality of being considered as a super-categorical noun for all subordinate concepts, to elide difference and connect units into a group.

    All set? Well, keep trying either way.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. (1) Assuming they do NOT sell at their value, this relationship becomes tendential rather than exact.

      hahaha... proving my point that vol. 3 causes this mystical mathematic B.S. based on transfer of value to fall like a house of cards. Good work, Comrade Hedlund.

      (2) "This is just the tendency resulting from the process of capital accumulation, "

      Wrong. Marx says it is a "**constant** tendency", not just some feeble "tendency" that never occurs in real life.

      According to you, it is a "tendency" mysteriously absent from the real world. Well, that means Marx's whole B.S. about capitalists gaining relative surplus value when wages fall just collapses and imploded. His theory has been refuted by you.

      You're on a roll today.

      (3) "Profit is one form of surplus value."

      No, it isn't. Surplus value doesn't exist.

      (4) You've never even adequately described how to overcome Marx's aggregate problem, or indeed shown you even properly understand the concept of SNLT in chapter 1 of vol. 1 of Capital. Instead, you wave your hands and say that the market mysteriously does it. Just like any neoclassical charlatan when confronted with problems about the natural rate of interest or the EMH.

      (5) you ignored the questions: if developed first world capitalism can provide soaring living standards even for workers (as it did even in the 19th century), then how can the “mass of misery, oppression, slavery, degradation, [sc. and] exploitation” be constantly growing? Why would socialism be inevitable if workers see their living standards soar and the real wage soars above subsistence level?

      (6) also, we know you're too cowardly to answer the question: Is your view that Marx's theory of wages is that real wages in the developed first world capitalism can and will rise above the value of the maintenance and reproduction of labour, and in the long run keep rising, vastly improving the living standards of workers?

      If so, then how can socialism be inevitable?

      Delete
    2. (1) Lol.

      (2) All social laws are tendencies. Some have more and some have fewer countervailing factors. I am sorry you're struggling with this so.

      (3) We are through the looking glass, here. You're actually denying the existence of the profit share, interest, and rent. Magnificent. You should show this level of bombastic foolishness more often, it's quite funny.

      (4) I have, actually. A) There is no aggregation problem because we're viewing labor in the abstract (like a capitalist does in his accounts, considering them quantitatively rather than qualitatively), and abstractions exist to elide particularities to create groupings of things. B) Averages.

      As usual, you're making this way more complicated than it actually is. Well, congratulations, the complicated theory you've constructed is wrong, as you've been trying so hard to show. The simpler one, however, is not.

      (5) I did answer, but I could have been clearer: Because not everyone can belong to the labor aristocracy; its existence is predicated on the proletarianization and exploitation of the third world. See, e.g., chart 1 here (though you may find the entire article of interest).

      (6) What is your definition of cowardly, exactly? Because I've answered this numerous times, only to have you delete my comment. Very brave of you, m'lord.

      "Can"? Yes. "Will"? Depends on quite a lot of factors, including the stability of imperialism, untold murders abroad, and, even then, the state of the class struggle still. If first-world wages "soar" indefinitely under capitalism, this will have been nothing to celebrate; the global cost will have been grave beyond imagining. And while this may put socialism far from the minds of satisfied first-worlders, those who make that satisfaction possible will not endure their lot forever. (Especially as we run out of new sources of cheap labor in the world, and the global economy grows all the more unstable.)

      Don't get it twisted; socialism is not "inevitable" as something that will happen independently of human intervention or desire. But the contradictions of capitalism will forever create the tendency for its own overcoming, and if humanity is to have any hope of survival, it'll have to happen.

      Delete
    3. (3) "We are through the looking glass, here. You're actually denying the existence of the profit share, interest, and rent."

      False. The laughable lies of an idiot troll, Hedlund. I don't deny the existence of money profits, or interest, or rent.

      I deny the existence of SNLT as a coherent and empirically relevant concept. Also the equally incoherent, empirically irrelevant and mystical notion of surplus labour value.

      Incidentally, modern businesses count rent and interest payments as part of their costs of production and include them in total average unit costs when calculating mark-up prices (Godley, Wynne and Marc Lavoie. 2007. Monetary Economics: An Integrated Approach to Credit, Money, Income, Production and Wealth. Palgrave Macmillan, New York, N.Y., p. 265) -- which refutes the Classical B.S. that rent and interest must be modelled as a residual of profits.

      Delete
    4. " And while this may put socialism far from the minds of satisfied first-worlders, those who make that satisfaction possible will not endure their lot forever"

      If it's true the Western World is developed and rich because of exploitation of the "Third World", why were most Western Europeans countries rich and prosper way before colonialism?

      Is there any empirical evidence supporting the thesis that developed countries are rich because they exploit the "Third World"?

      I'm honestly asking.

      Delete
    5. The prosperity of Western countries that never had colonies (e.g. Switzerland, Finland) would also need some explaining. Alternatively, you could seek an explanation listing the technological innovations that arose in Western Europe from 1600 to the present day.


      Delete
    6. why were most Western Europeans countries rich and prosper way before colonialism?

      Early adoption of manufacturing, and early expansion of markets within and among themselves, plus foreign colonies, covers much of the ground, I gather. Colonialism is one of the key factors that essentially created the "third world" as we know it, and given the movement of wealth and people geographically, it's not hard to see how immediate trading partners also benefit from colonies of their neighbors.

      Is there any empirical evidence supporting the thesis that developed countries are rich because they exploit the "Third World"?

      Zak Cope has been doing some very good contemporary analysis on the transfer of value from the third to the first, such as in this article or this book.

      Delete
    7. "Zak Cope has been doing some very good contemporary analysis on the transfer of value from the third to the first, such as in this article or this book."


      Is what is written in the article above true, LK?




      Delete
    8. Anonymous@March 9, 2016 at 2:57 PM

      (1) first of all, no, Hedlund doesn't refute my point because real wages in capitalism soared from 1840s to the early 1980s -- long before this offshoring of manufacturing to the third world happened.

      Secondly, Hedlund days:

      "Early adoption of manufacturing, and early expansion of markets within and among themselves, plus foreign colonies, covers much of the ground, I gather"

      The early adoption of manufacturing in the West didn't require colonialism. Also, nor were colonies a necessary condition for the industrial revolution.

      This has been demonstrated by Bairoch.

      (2) Hedlund is referring to this:

      Torkil Lauesen and Zak Cope, "Imperialism and the Transformation of Values into Prices," Monthly Review 67.3 (July-August), 2015.
      http://monthlyreview.org/2015/07/01/imperialism-and-the-transformation-of-values-into-prices/

      No, the central thesis in that article is nothing but Marxist B.S. about abstract socially necessary labour time and surplus value -- these concepts aren't even coherent or definable, and they are empirically irrelevant.

      The only worthwhile point there is that a great deal of manufacturing has been shipped off to the Third world since the 1980s. True. This is because businesses like to cut costs, not because they are in search of mystical surplus labour value.

      However, missing from this is that in some countries like Taiwan, South Korea and Japan the growth of industries there have raised real per capita GDP massively and these countries have become rich like the West and workers' rights and living standards have also massively increased.

      In other parts of the world there is real exploitation, but there is nothing necessary about any of this. Governments and consumer populations in the West can punish their businesses and even multinationals for exploitation and make them improve their working conditions.

      Under a return to post-WWII policies, third world governments can use infant industry protectionism and industrial policy, and implement labour rights. This requires political change.

      A lot of manufacturing can be brought back to the West with automation and robotics, and this will eventually happen in the third world too. Their problem will be one of getting the technology, resources, and human skills necessary for rapid development.

      Delete
  2. "But the contradictions of capitalism will forever create the tendency for its own overcoming, and if humanity is to have any hope of survival, it'll have to happen."

    So wait: So humanity will prosper under lunatic Marxist totalitarian states with gulags, secret police, show trials, mass murder and communist imperialism? Good luck with that Comrade Hedcase!

    ReplyDelete
  3. (5) is B.S. We saw this in the golden age of capitalism (1940s-1970s), when even the third world prospered and poverty was reduced considerably there when the right macro policies were pursued.

    Also, the soaring post-WWII success of quite a few third world states like South Korea, Japan, Singapore, Hong Kong, and Taiwan demonstrates perfectly well that your crackpot Leninist fables about imperialism are false.

    ReplyDelete
  4. (4) lol. So SNLT values and surplus labour values are a purely imaginary B.S. inside your crackpot Marxist mind?

    Thanks for that Comrade Hedlund!

    ReplyDelete
  5. (1) some supposed tendencies do not exist. E.g., the tendency of light to propagate in the aether. Doesn't exist empirically. Just like the LTV, chump.

    ReplyDelete