Friday, July 12, 2013

Mises and Keynes on Probability

Ludwig van den Hauwe (2011; see Hauwe 2008, for an earlier version of the paper) makes the claim that Ludwig von Mises’s views on probability have a close affinity with those of Keynes, rather than with the views of his brother Richard von Mises. This view is in contrast to that of Hoppe (2007).

Hauwe sees two fundamental conceptual divisions in probability theory (Hauwe 2011: 472), which I expand upon below:
(1) Epistemological (or epistemic) probability theory, further divided into
(i.) the logical interpretation;
(ii.) the subjective interpretation;
(iii.) the intersubjective interpretation, and
(2) Objective probability theory, further divided into
(i.) the frequency interpretation;
(ii.) the propensity interpretation.
(Gillies 2000: 2).
An epistemological/epistemic probability assignment measures a degree of knowledge, a degree of rational belief, or a degree of belief (Hauwe 2011: 473).

In contrast, objective probability interpretations see probability assignments as a characteristic of the material world (Hauwe 2011: 473).

Hauwe (2011: 473) charges that many members of the Austrian school (such as Rothbard 2004: 553) have simply assumed that Mises adopted the frequentist interpretation of probability of his brother Richard von Mises, when Ludwig von Mises really ascribed to an epistemological/epistemic probability interpretation.

Richard von Mises’s frequentism held that probabilities are based on collectives or sets of things, events, or phenomena, and formulated his limiting frequency definition of probability.

Hauwe stresses:
“An important implication of Richard von Mises’s frequency theory is that, when dealing with unique events, statistical or stochastic methods will be essentially useless. Where collectives do not exist, probability theory and the calculations based on it will add nothing to our knowledge concerning the world of reality. Only where previous experience has established that events can be considered as belonging to a collective, can statistical methods play a role.” (Hauwe 2011: 484).
And furthermore,
“Richard von Mises thus advocated a monist view of probability, that is, he asserts that there is only one concept of probability that is of scientific importance, in contradistinction to his brother Ludwig von Mises who espoused a dualist view of probability.” (Hauwe 2011: 486, n. 24).
According to Hauwe, Keynes adopted a logical interpretation of probability. Keynes argued that probability is a degree of partial entailment, but primarily in regard to propositions, and involving a logic of inductive reasoning. Thus Keynes conceived of probability as “a branch of logic” (Hauwe 2011: 488).

There is some confusion over the question whether Keynes’s theory was a subjective or objective one. But Keynes himself thought that “probability was [sc. a] degree of rational belief not simply degree of belief” (Hauwe 2011: 488). Therefore his theory must be understood as having a strong objective element.

Hauwe summarises the differences between Richard von Mises and Keynes on the fundamental nature of probability as follows:
Richard von Mises
– held that probability is a branch of empirical science;
– held that probability is to be defined as a limiting frequency;
– held that the axioms of probability are obtained by abstraction from two empirical laws;
– held that the only scientifically important theory of probability is the frequentist interpretation.

Keynes
– held that probability is a logic of induction, and thus an extension of deductive logic;
– held that probability is a degree of rational belief;
– held that the axioms of probability are perceived by direct logical intuition;
– held a broader definition of probability beyond mere relative frequencies. (Hauwe 2011: 489).
The following crucial difference is seen by Hauwe:
”For Richard von Mises only probabilities defined within an empirical collective can be evaluated and only these probabilities have any scientific interest. The remaining uses of probability are examples of a crude prescientific concept towards which he takes a dismissive attitude. For Keynes on the other hand all probabilities are essentially on a par. They all obey the same formal rules and play the same role in our thinking. Certain special features of the situation allow us to assign numerical values in some cases, though not in general. Through the acknowledgement that frequency probability does not cover all we mean by probability, Keynes’s position is thus also closer to that of other economists such as Ludwig von Mises and John Hicks. Finally the position of statistics is different in the two accounts. For von Mises it is a study of how to apply probability theory in practice, similar to applied mechanics. For Keynes statistical inference is a special kind of inductive inference and statistics is a branch of the theory of induction.” (Hauwe 2011: 497).
Now Ludwig von Mises’s notion of “class probability” appears to correspond to Richard von Mises’s frequency probability (Hauwe 2011: 500), but Hauwe contends that ultimately Ludwig von Mises held an epistemological/epistemic view of probability:
“On the one hand Ludwig von Mises clearly relates the idea of probability to the state of knowledge of the knowing subject. This is true both of class probability and of case probability. A statement is probable if our knowledge concerning its content is deficient. This view is shared by all adepts of an epistemological interpretation of the concept of probability, including John Maynard Keynes. Richard von Mises, to the contrary, very explicitly rejects the idea that the concept of probability refers to a state of partial or deficient knowledge. On the other hand, Ludwig von Mises clearly recognizes that the meaning of probability is different according to the field of knowledge in which it is used or according to the kind of phenomena to which it is applied. He thus embraces a dualist view in the philosophy of probability. But in this respect his view is again clearly different from and opposed to that of his brother Richard von Mises who obviously embraces a monist theory of probability.” (Hauwe 2011: 489)
Hauwe contends that Ludwig von Mises regarded his category of “case probability” as “important scientific status” (Hauwe 2011: 500). But Mises held that case probability can never be given a strict numerical value, and Keynes also thought that many probabilities are not capable of numerical estimate, and in some case cannot be ranked on an ordinal scale (Hauwe 2011: 501).


BIBLIOGRAPHY
Gillies, Donald. 2000. Philosophical Theories of Probability. Routledge, London and New York.

Hauwe, Ludwig van den. 2008. “John Maynard Keynes and Ludwig von Mises on Probability,” Procesos De Mercado Revista Europea de Economía Política 5.1: 11–50.
http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1607122

Hauwe, Ludwig van den. 2011. “John Maynard Keynes and Ludwig von Mises on Probability,” Journal of Libertarian Studies 22: 471–507.

Hoppe, Hans-Hermann. 2007. “The Limits of Numerical Probability: Frank H. Knight and Ludwig von Mises and the Frequency Interpretation,” Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 10.1: 1–20.

Mises, L. 1998. Human Action: A Treatise on Economics. The Scholar’s Edition. Mises Institute, Auburn, Ala.

Rothbard, M. N. 2004. Man, Economy, and State, The Scholar’s Edition. Ludwig von Mises Institute, Auburn, Ala.

6 comments:

  1. "An epistemological/epistemic probability assignment measures a degree of knowledge, a degree of rational belief, or a degree of belief (Hauwe 2011: 473).

    In contrast, objective probability interpretations see probability assignments as a characteristic of the material world (Hauwe 2011: 473)."

    If this is what he says then I think he's wrong. What he calls objective probability interpretations have nothing to do with the "material world". I can believe in "objective probability" -- i.e. that probabilities are knowable -- and reject the idea of a "material world".

    This debate has nothing to do with materialism versus idealism but rather if the universe -- however one defines it -- is characterised by massive amounts of potentially knowable probabilities that are numerical or whether it is not like this at all and is, instead, uncertain. This has more to do with determinism versus non-determinism than it has to do with materialism versus idealism.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Let's say that Copenhagen interpretation of quantum physics is correct (for the sake of the argument) and results of wave-function collapse are truly random and non-deterministic. In that case, we may say that there is no imaginable way to predict the next result of an experiment like a double-slit experiment, it's outcome is uncertain. But we still could use probabilities (of the frequency kind) and it is pretty obvious that the results will converge to 50/50 given infinitely many experiments.

      I'd like to argue that probabilities are still useful even in non-deterministic world, though I have to state that I'm not a physicist and I am uncertain of which quantum theory interpretation is correct.

      Delete
    2. I don't think you understand what we mean by "uncertain". We mean a situation in which probabilities are useless. So your example is ruled out by definition.

      That doesn't mean that probabilities are then useless everywhere. But they are useless in most areas of the human sciences.

      Delete
    3. No, I was not implying anything about the materialism versus idealism issue. Ludwig von Mises was a determinist; Richard von Mises was not. I was only paraphrasing Richard von Mises. See the quote in footnote. But all were probably sharing an implicit presupposition that materialism is true...

      Delete
    4. You have written a fascinating paper, Ludwig.

      Do you have any idea of how Mises regarded the probability of general inductive inferences (that is, non-objective, non-numeric probabilities from inductive reasoning)?, e.g,. how do we estimate the probability of "Napoleon was defeated at Waterloo").

      Did Mises, for example, think they had rough, approximate, non-numerical estimates only?

      If so, there is another similarity with Keynes, even though Keynes thought that such general inductive probabilities, on the basis of a weight of evidence, could be represented as approximate intervals, but not single numbers, and not with the status of objective a priori probability. Often such probabilities are incomparable and cannot ranked, and do not obey the axioms of the probability calculus.

      Delete
  2. A Nice pic by Unlearningecon on methodology-Milton Friedman’s Distortions, Part II
    http://unlearningeconomics.wordpress.com/2013/07/12/milton-friedmans-distortions-part-ii/

    ReplyDelete